Wall in English

Index


Visiting Agora, Notes by Maija Lanas

Note 1: polo players and a ball
Ever since I was a doctoral student in the national doctoral school in Education, my peers from the south (especially from Helsinki) have seemed intimidating to me, not only because many questions that were relevant to a northern researcher seemed to change shape when brought into discussions with the south, but also because my peers from Helsinki were always so quick, so focused, and they never hesitated biting their teeth into each other’s work. More than once I listened to them talking in plain Finnish, not comprehending what they were talking about. Before my last seminar in the doctoral school I dreamt that my presentation overlapped with a polo game which took place in the same room, and in my dream I was trying to present while polo players circled around me curiously testing with their sticks if I was a ball.

So, as I prepared for the visit, I prepared for observing ruthless academic debates of a wolf pack mentality. Turns out, my preparations were in vain. I saw neither sharp teeth nor polo sticks.

Note 2: nakedness and national identity?
In the seminars I have had the pleasure of reading and discussing so many interesting high quality works during this autumn that I feel intellectually nourished. I look forward to reading what the researchers within Agora produce in the coming years. One piece that completely threw me off my treaded path was Tuure Vaahtera’s emerging work which makes a case for nakedness as a part of national identity and nakedness as a part of ability to swim. Immensely fascinating work that forces us to rethink what we think we know.

Note 3: decentering human intentions
November 24th I gave a lecture about the implicit constraints on teachers’ work in Finland, arguing that Finnish teachers are not quite as free as they seem to be. I highlighted that the focus on discourse decenters individuals; that the lack of teacher freedom does not occur because of any individual school, teacher, principal or teacher educator, but because of how discourses operate, and because of the unintentional “side-effects”. This is a message I sometimes struggle to transmit. In the modernist, humanist understanding effects are in some way traceable to intentions of human agents, whereas the “post” approaches allow discussing the effects without tracing them back to human intentions. There is a need in education for a theoretical language that would not immediately take us to the question of ‘who’.

Note 4: blunt intelligence?
In the feminist methodologies seminar (28.29.11.2016) Eva Bendix Petersen gave an interesting lecture in which she questioned some aspects of the posthumanist work. She drew an example from an article I had read, and the questions she asked were much like the questions I had asked with some posthumanist researchers in the past year.
The way I see it is that the article which was discussed, just like any article, does not stop when it is written, but it continues inviting responses, reactions, negotiations, and every reader/negotiator engages in their own terms. At times some authors might wish for some negotiations more than others, but they all emerge nevertheless. In the weeks after prof. Petersen’s lecture, as the discussion evolved in different contexts, and several interesting themes emerged:

  • What is political? How do we define political research? If the political implications cannot be directly drawn from research, is it non-political?
  • How do we critique research? Do new approaches require new forms of critique? Does all research need to be critiqued, or could it be enough that it is built on, by those to whom it makes sense? What if one’s way of building is through critique?
  • What are the differences between rules of social conduct and academic conduct? Can one’s work critiqued behind one’s back? Where are the backs and fronts in academic world?
  • Intelligence is often associated with sharp things and sharp adjectives. It is quick, edgy, brave at the face of conflicts, not shying away from confrontations. For a while I’ve been exploring with the thought of dull intelligence: what is left of an argument if its edges are sanded, and if there is no spear to point at anything. I’m still figuring it out.

Posted on the 21st of December 2016.


Riikka Hohti and Hanna Guttorm are at the International Congress of Qualitative Inquiry.

Rikka Hohti’s greetings from the 11th International Congress of Qualitative Inquiry, Illinois

The conference here is slowly starting. Yesterday there was a panel discussion between Yvonna S. Lincoln, Ann Merete Otterstad, Harry Torrance, Maggie MacLure and Norman Denzin (these people do really exist!) who discussed the need of critical methodologies that won’t rely on normative science, or using it in ways that resist. Qualitative research as a political and activist force was an issue here, too. The conference theme this year is Constructing a new critical inquiry.

Some flashes of the discussion:

Harry Torrance: Science is about curiosity, not only definitive proof. It is peculiar that the researcher’s focus on proof seems to be so much more important than possibilities.

Ann Merete Otterstad: There is no knowledge to be found out there. You have to start where you live and work.

Maggie: Why critque has somehow become a problem for materially engaged sholars? One problem is that intentionality and consciousness might not be only human. The ways of criticaliy that are familiar now precondition the human subject and produces those who know and those who are known. We are immersed in the assemblages that we are trying to master. Second, criticality is often a backward looking business, not interested in asking what comes next? Critique could be a combination of care and a kind of recklessness. Not simply being categorising and judging.

Norman Denzin: I can become an agent in the kind of change I want to. Writing as a way of being in the world. Before, we used to be reading culture over the shoulders of the natives we studied. It was textualism. The stories and the aticles in journals that we publis have a minimal impact.

Yvonna Lincoln: Teach about conflicts, the latest arguments, try to make students aware these are not simple and unproblematic.

Maggie: We noticed that through conventional argumentative styles of convincing we often ended up reinforcing old assumptions. Instead, we found powerful ways of convincing through working with artists in ways in which people were not told “this is the right way to think, this is how you should think.”

Critical in a nutshell?

Maggie: Who is helped and who is hurt? In new materialist ethics you don’t stop with the question so that you are the one who notices and knows. The capacity to affect and to be affected.. Who benefits?

Harry: In whose interest a particular activty is taken? Not a single answer. To leave the illusion that what we do, has anticipated consequenses. There is not one single version of social justice.

riikkahohti


BOOK REVIEW

Ansgar Allen
Benign Violence: Education in and beyond the age of reason
Palgrave Macmillan
1BSN 978-1-27285-0
pp289

Kathryn Ecclestone, Professor of Education, University of Sheffield[1]

I’m writing the first draft of this review on December 18th 2014, the evening before academics across Britain learn their fate at the hands of the latest ‘research excellence framework’ (REF) which is run by the Higher Education Funding Council. This 20 year old, 5-yearly assessment audit of universities’ research outputs has become a constantly ratcheting, increasingly oppressive Hydra. It is an especially stark outcome of the intertwined rise of examination, its illusions of meritocracy and liberal attempts to ameliorate their inequalities, that, as this book shows so compellingly, drives the entire British education system, the bodies in it, and those who examine, assess, select, stratify, filter out and fail those bodies.

*          *          *          *

The next day. So, it turns out that we did well and those of us who are critical of its pernicious effects found ourselves pleased at succeeding, caught up in congratulations about how good we are. Believing, or perhaps performing our meritocratic belief, that we had ‘deserved’ our good results, we suspended our reservations about both the flawed assessment process and the ways in which the REF outcomes can be spun every which way to suit particular readings of its league tables.

*          *          *          *

Like all performative systems, REF gets into the body, mind and heart. It has turned some of its participants and advocates into enthusiastic evangelists. For many, it has become a moral imperative because its league table rankings affect jobs, promotion prospects and the intensifying competition for ever-diminishing research grants. Others are cynical compliers, including many of us drawn into administering and managing the many-headed monster. Allen’s book illuminates a long liberal-progressive educational tradition of delusion about meritocracy. Following his argument, attempts to wrest some authenticity and decency from the insane game that the REF has become are just another useless manifestation of delusion.

*          *          *          *

For Allen, the celebrations belie something more malign. “Worse than the carnival, perhaps, is a form of malevolent simplicity that pervades institutional life. Principles and procedures designed ostensibly to protect us are dogmatically followed. This happy simplicity allows one’s co-workers and superiors to rest content and ignore the complex violence of the workplace. Educators and other professionals are particularly vulnerable, as this violence most often feeds on and manipulates the educational conscience they have been forced to internalise” (p246, original emphasis).

According to this book, all meritocratic systems are violent. The REF is no exception: it ruins careers, turning increasing numbers of academics into REFugees excluded from selection because their research is allegedly not high quality enough. Some are made redundant. Many of us have become anxious and passive, even, to use one of Allen’s hard hitting observations, ‘bovine’.

*          *          *          *

As he waits in an airport departure lounge, Allen wonders “where is it that we learn to behave as cattle, to submit ourselves to this social ritual[standing in line early to make sure we board] as we collectively respond to its externally set, internally processed demands? We are all anxious, of course. There are no allocated seats on board” (pxvii).

*          *          *          *

I’m writing this review in the style of the book.

*          *          *          *

Discrete sections alternate between flowing and disjointed, short and long, with detailed historical accounts of examination and meritocracy in the British education system interrupted by examples from our times. Allen’s acute interruptions aim to unsettle the reader, stopping her from being lulled along in lazy or complacent agreement or disagreement in the way that, he argues, conventional academic writing encourages. Sometimes he challenges or questions the reader directly. There are few references: Allen is dismissive of academic conventions that demand the bolstering of argument with endless reference to others’ work; a demand that, he argues cleverly, creates ‘academic thickness’. His Foucauldian analysis does not lead, as it seems often in academic writing, to meandering, dense text that makes sense only to fellow Foucauldians. Instead, his prose is well crafted, sparing and provocative.

*          *          *          *

So the book proceeds in its forensic, imaginative, relentlessly gloomy genealogy. It charts the intertwining of examination and meritocracy and attempts by some educators to appropriate them for progressive ends. It reveals the ways in which the British education system has evolved to justify and manage the fact that, for the vast majority of the population in it, there are no allocated seats on board. Or, at least, not in the much-prized courses and institutions that, for a minority, are a passport to a better future.

*          *          *          *

In the week after the REF, I’m returning from abroad. Allen’s airport observation comes to mind as I wait in line for the ritual humiliation of security and its random and ridiculous searchings. Meritocracies don’t just have to manage exclusion and selection. They must also instil a constant fear of being found lacking, perhaps of being exposed as a chancer or a fraud; someone who doesn’t really deserve her or his place. Or simply as a threat to security.

*          *          *          *

Allen connects the ways in which different bodies, as well as whole populations, have been subjected to various forms of examination, particularly the scrutiny and harder edged assessments of late 19th/early 20th century eugenicists. Here ideas and practices associated with meritocracy have produced ever-finer grained selection methods for jobs, armed service and education. They cannot be divorced from eugenics. Yet unlike educators who deem themselves to be ‘progressive’, Allen does not regard eugenics as some past horror that can never be allowed to return. Instead, in its ‘direct coercive intervention into the sphere of human existence’ (p135), he makes a wider point, namely that ‘in the analysis of power we must not overlook the mundane by focusing on the extreme, for it is in the mundane and everyday that we find the more treacherous operations of power ’ (p135). It is the processes of examination and assessment that are so powerful now, far more so than their outcomes.

*          *          *          *

For Allen, the distinction between examination as scrutiny, inspection, investigation to establish the truth or qualities of an object, and assessment as a vehicle for distribution and reward, a way of valuing and distributing human worth is important. The terms are not therefore synonymous, even if they are invariably used that way in everyday discourse. The distinction helps to explain how traces of old eugenics re-emerge in obsession with the “current ecological status of a population, rather than its prior genetic basis or future possibility” (p210).

It is not therefore tenable simply to denounce the inequities and tyrannies of examination and assessment, as many liberal, progressive, radical and critical educators do before proposing to replace them more holistic and child-centred assessment processes, more realistic aspirations, more authentic and ‘just’ measures of outcomes such as ‘value-added’. Instead, examination is not so easily grasped as a history that we can understand better and then free ourselves from it with new, more progressive methods. Nor is examination a simple monolith: “at any one time, it is distributed across a whole series of arrangements, as a shifting set of functions. To grasp the significance of examination, we must pursue it in all its diffusion… the examination of human worth and mapping of its social distribution has a past worth visiting (pxiv/v).

*          *          *          *

Its sophisticated genealogical approach and telling historical photographs of unwitting subjects of examination and assessment make the book much more than a history of this intertwining. Instead, rooted in eugenics, examination and meritocracy are inextricably linked as evolving forms of power. Allen’s analysis exposes the subtle, often contradictory ways in which these forms of power work, inside and outside bodies. He charts their shifting influence on post-war goals and especially those championed by liberal progressives, from the unashamedly stratified opportunities created by the 1944 Education Act and justified by Labour and Conservative policy makers as a way of ensuring that working class children knew their destiny for unskilled and labouring jobs, through brief flirtation with a comprehensive system in the 1970s, and then to calls for ‘parity of esteem’, equality of opportunity, widening access and participation from the 1980s onwards.

A fluid meritocracy serves what is now seen as the natural ecology of human existence, in which each individual strives towards the realisation of his or her individual potential” (p244). This contemporary version of acceptable aspiration has generated the inflated ceremonies and celebrations held for successful examinees today, and the parallel rise of liberal-progressive interest in more holistic assessments of the ‘whole’ child, the ‘real’ child, the truly authentic child, its personal development and, increasingly, its emotional development.

The book exposes liberal delusions that it’s possible to personalise, soften and make fairer ranking, selection, over-testing and target-setting as benign violence. This is a strong and original critique. In particular, Allen demolishes the highly influential academic movement that has championed ‘assessment for learning’ and a process-driven education. Its goals for a culture of success go much further, as Allen observes, than well-intentioned feedback from teachers. Instead, old 19th century forms of peer and self assessment and cooperative learning reappear in new guises, as new ways of socialising individuals to work “in an environment of individual striving without the pernicious effects rivalry…trained in the techniques of cooperative activity whilst atomised within practices of self-enhancement’ (p238).

*          *          *          *

I am ‘impact coordinator’ for the 2020 REF.   At our celebratory meeting, a colleague asks me how I will improve the rating we got for impact in this one (our case studies, it seems, were given a 4*, 100% score). As a joke, I’m tempted to offer the typical football manager’s response that the team will give 110%. But I mention instead my little resistance against the patronising and demeaning title of ‘champions’ that the university wanted for its impact coordinators. The iron grip of examination and apparent meritocracy encourages the self-deluding comfort of such small, smart-arse symbols of ‘victory’.

*          *          *          *

Actually, as any Foucauldian knows, it’s much worse than mere self-delusion. Liberal progressives who cling to meritocracy and don’t see our ‘period as one in which disorder and the impossibility of fairness are principles that have been elevated above their opposites and incorporated within governmental technique’ (p10, original emphasis), are integral to insidious discourses and processes of governance.

Allen’s focus on this well-meaning group of educators is compelling and controversial. The delusion that more holistic assessment processes are progressive overlooks the ways in which …. “today we live amongst the residues of welfare reform, occupying a broken landscape from which we draw meaning. Our memories of a former system – of the institutions and dreams of the welfare state – play a crucial role in the regime that is its replacement. Hence, to speak of the destruction of the welfare state is to exaggerate the case. Welfare has been destroyed only to the extent to which it has been co-opted and absorbed….put to more effective use by new frameworks of power” (p191-2).

*          *          *          *

Allen observes that assessment’s current reach and effects are more profound than ever before “….once the social engineer retreats, only those who believe improvement is a perpetual possibility can be depended on to make the effort required to constantly reposition themselves in the social hierarchy” (p237). The focus now is on ‘the hapless ways of helpless children’ (p237). Modified, adapted eugenics appears again: ‘the vulnerable child must become resilient rather than rebellious’ (ibid).

This resonates powerfully with my own critique of the inexorable rise of universal social and emotional learning interventions. In the spirit of modified eugenics, positive psychologists evangelise about programmes to train children, young people and adults in the mindsets, dispositions and ‘skills’ of ‘emotional well-being’ under the previous government, and ‘character’ under this one. Such claims lead instrumental behaviourists and equally instrumental liberal and progressive educators to present ‘resilience’ as one of many essential dispositions that we can and should teach. Across the education system, ever-more intrusive informal and formal assessments of the minds and hearts of children, young people and adults are new forms of governance that create and then respond to new disordered and emotionally troubled identities.

*          *          *          *

In the week before Christmas, the head of Britain’s 149 job-centres[2] tweets a stream of seemingly banal bon mots from positive psychology to her staff. One seems spookily apposite for the REF shenanigans: “be fired with enthusiasm or be fired with enthusiasm”. In his forthcoming book ‘The happiness industry: how government and big business sold us well-being’, William Davies argues that the growing trend for companies to require workers to take part in well-being programmes is a response to worsening levels of disaffection and stress-related illnesses amongst employees. Some human resource managers propose sacking workers who either resist them, or are simply critical (Davies 2015).

In a tightening circular grip, the bossy bon mots of the job centres director are far from banal: instead, the nasty, increasingly blatant tentacles of the drive to assess our emotional responses, dispositions and attitudes now entangle our inner feelings and responses to the assessment systems that govern us.

*          *          *          *

For me, this book signals that be positive or suffer the consequences is the logical outcome of attempts by progressive educators to humanise the expanding reach of assessment in meritocracies. Perhaps Allen hopes that be cynical or suffer the consequences helps us understand the schizophrenic tyrannies and benefits of examination and assessment and the price we pay for progressive delusions.   In the Foucauldian gloom of his moral high ground, there is no blueprint for action, nor any optimism that any aspect of education is emancipatory or benign. Instead, in the last line of his book, he tells us that his aim is to get under our skin, to excoriate, to trouble us to resistance.

*          *          *          *

I see his point but I’m not sure what response it warrants. Allen presents genealogy as an incitement, an incomplete engagement in combat “without intellectual restraint… an insurrectional device, designed for rebellion” (p247). He concludes by saying that rebelling against out educational present requires us to “explore its perversions, its cynicisms”, to “ disabuse ourselves of our well-meaning but shallow commitments” (p250). Yet if hoping for some, any, progressive possibilities is futile, there is no chance either of collective resistance to the tyrannies Allen charts so relentlessly.

So I consider some tiny ones. As the next REF grinds into action, I’ll ask colleagues to read two articles published in the Times Higher Education in December 2014: Allen’s critique of research impact and a truly excoriating, militant account of the REF by a professor of cultural history who excluded his own research from assessment as a protest against its inequities and corruptions (Allen 2014, Sayer 2014).

And yet I remain both pessimistic and cynical ….. if liberal delusions enable meritocracy to function better, indeed are essential to its functioning, surely resistances and excoriations do the same. We can resist a little – and then it’s governance as usual.

 

References

Allen, A. 2014. Who benefits from the impact agenda? Times Higher Education, 6th November 2014

Davies, W. 2015. The happiness industry: how government and big business sold us well-being, London: Verso

Sayer, D. 2014. One scholar’s crusade against the REF, Times Higher Education, 11th December 2014

[1] This is an amended version of a book review submitted to the Journal of Education Policy.

[2] These are centres funded by the Department of Work and Pensions to offer support, advice and guidance to unemployed people of all ages.


Practices for the “New” in the New Empiricisms, the New Materialisms, and Post Qualitative Inquiry

A lecture by  Professor Elizabeth Adams St.Pierre on November 18th 2014 at University of Helsinki

Several years ago I introduced the concept, post qualitative inquiry (St.Pierre, 2011a), to destabilize what I’ve called “conventional humanist qualitative inquiry,” which I argue has become overdetermined in the U.S. by the publishing industry, university research courses, and journals and books that detail very carefully exactly what qualitative methodology is and how to do it. As John Law (2004) explained, “particular sets of rules and procedures may be questioned and debated, but the overall need for proper rules and procedures is not. It is taken for granted that these are necessary” (p. 5). To me, it is ironic that so much qualitative research has become formalized, precise, and methods-driven because it was invented in the 1980s (e.g., Denzin, 1989; Erickson, 1986; Lincoln & Guba, 1985) as an interpretive social science—drawing from the larger interpretive turn and, especially, from interpretive anthropology (e.g. Geertz, 1973)—to deliberately counter the methods-driven approach of positivist social science. Interpretive social science, unlike positivism, argues that method can’t guarantee validity and that any “finding” is simply an interpretation which rests on other interpretations, not on the Cartesian bedrock of uncontested truth.

In education, in particular, the scientifically-based, evidence-based research movement initiated by the 2002 U.S. No Child Left Behind Act (NCLB) contributed to the tightening up of the so-called emergent nature of qualitative methodology. In particular, NCLB created a new funding agency for educational research, the U.S. Institute of Education Sciences (note how easily education became a science), and its goal was to fund causal research using its gold standard, the randomized controlled trial, that supposedly proves beyond a doubt “what works” in schools, thereby shifting our focus—even in qualitative methodology—from interpretation and contingency to causation and final truth.   As a result, we now have a great deal of positivist qualitative research, which is not surprising because as George Steinmetz (2005) noted, positivism is the “epistemological unconscious” of the social sciences in the U.S.; and 1980s qualitative methodology never did rid itself of positivist concepts like validity, bias, subjectivity, triangulation, coding data, audit trails, inter-rater reliability, and so on. The positivism always embedded in qualitative methodology now thrives. For example, I receive a steady flood of emails inviting me to learn how to code qualitative data using various computer software programs, a practice I argue is unthinkable in interpretive social science, much less postmodern work. And I despair when doctoral students’ response to questions about their dissertation research is something like, “I’m doing a case study” or “I’m doing an autoethnography” or “I’m doing an interview study.” In other words, they respond with a “research design.” When I ask them what theories they’re thinking with in their studies, they seldom respond coherently. It appears they’ve studied some kind of stripped down methodology (or more accurately, they’ve learned some research methods) but not epistemology or ontology. I believe this is a failure to teach, not necessarily a failure to learn.

Of course, the creeping control of U.S. Institutional Reviews Boards (IRB) that monitor our research to protect human subjects seldom understand qualitative methodology have contributed to its positivism by requiring researchers to follow bizarre practices such as signing their own consent forms to do autoethnographic research.

But in 2014, the U.S. National Research Council (NRC) released a committee report (available free from the U.S. National Academy Press website) that proposed revisions to our federal law. This report is sponsored not only by the National Research Council committee organized for the purpose but also by other prestigious national committees as well as the American Educational Research Association. In my reading of the report, it appears that much qualitative research will either be exempt from IRB review or expedited. This is certainly good news for qualitative researchers. Of course, we’ll have to wait and see whether the proposed recommendations are included in the revision of the federal law, but if they are, they could eventually help loosen up the structure of qualitative research in the U.S. Interestingly, I have already heard quite a bit of resistance to the proposed revisions from qualitative researchers, which is not surprising, given how quickly we accept current dominant, disciplinary structures as normal, necessary, and good.

But there is always resistance to the excess of power. Even as much educational research was taken over by the State Science Machine at the beginning of this century thereby quantifying students and teachers as well as research methodology, others in the humanities and social sciences shifted from Western Enlightenment humanism’s epistemological rage for knowledge that guides methods-driven qualitative methodology with all its “practices of formalization” (Pascale, 2011, p. 17) to the ontological—the nature of being—which I believe qualitative methodology mostly avoids. In conventional humanist qualitative methodology, to be is to know.

This new work has organized itself differently as affect theory (Gregg & Seigworth, 2010), thing theory (Brown, 2001), actor network theory (Latour, 2005), assemblage theory (De Landa, 2006), the new materialism (Coole & Frost, 2010), the new empiricism (Clough, 2009), and the posthuman (Braidotti, 2013). But I argue that poststructural theorists including Derrida, Foucault, Lyotard, Baudrillard and, especially, Deleuze and Guattari, very clearly addressed ontological issues and the material half a century ago. For example, last year I re-read with my doctoral students Foucault’s Archaeology of Knowledge (1971/1972) and The Order of Things (1966/1970), and we found ontology and the material everywhere. And how could one say that Derrida, with his critique of presence, neglects the ontological, which explains why Vicki Kirby (2011) and Karen Barad (2010) make good use of Derrida in their “new” work.

Much of the new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative work uses the ontology of Deleuze and Guattari, who offer a constellation of imbricated concepts (e.g., rhizome, assemblage, plane of consistency, refrain, diagram) that enable a different ontology and their transcendental empiricism. Working with DeleuzoGuattarian concepts is not easy. For example, one can’t understand a concept like diagram without understanding others it works with— assemblage, abstract machine, plane of consistency, Body without Organs—and they constantly introduce new concepts. In addition, a concept that is primary in one text, for example, sense in Deleuze’s book, Logic of Sense (1969/1990), may not be used again.

We have been slow to take up Deleuze’s and Deleuze and Guattari’s ontology in the U.S. social sciences not only because, as Lyotard (1979/1984) noted, “we are stuck in the positivism of this or that discipline” (p. 41), but also because their work was translated into English later than other 20th century French theorists. Deleuze visited the U.S. only once, whereas Foucault and Derrida were frequent, popular lecturers, and translations of their work were quickly available. Most importantly, Deleuze and Guattari’s work is deliberately ontological and difficult for those of us who’ve been so obsessed with methodology and epistemology that we’ve neglected to study ontology.

For those reasons, I believe this new empirical work that uses Deleuze and Guattari is difficult to think because we have to learn new language that is incompatible with the ontological grids of intelligibility that structure humanist methodologies. And it’s also difficult to do because there are no prescribed “methods” to follow or textbooks that offer, say, four handy research designs for new empirical research. If such a book were written, it would be contrary to the very image of thought Deleuze and Guattari created.

About method, Deleuze and Guattari (1980/1987) wrote that “a ‘method is the striated space of the cogitatio universalis and draws a path that must be followed from one point to another” (p. 377). In other words, the very idea of method forces one into a prescribed order of thought and practices that prohibits the experimental nature of transcendental empiricism. Method proscribes and prohibits. It controls and disciplines. Further, method always comes too late, is immediately out-of-date and so inadequate to the task at hand. But method not only can’t keep up with events, more seriously, it prevents them from coming into existence. One might say that “method,” as we think of it in the methodological individualism of conventional humanist qualitative methodology with its methods of data collection and methods of data analysis, cannot be thought or done in new empirical inquiry.

The most popular method of data collection in conventional humanist qualitative methodology is the face-to-face interview with its privileging of the authentic voice of the unique individual, the person, the human of humanism (for critiques, see St.Pierre, 2008, 2011b); but Deleuze and Guattari were not interested in the speaking subject as Lecercle (2002) explained in the following quotation:

The detailed study of an everyday discussion or telephone conversation yields trivial and uninteresting results, for such everyday exchanges are fully functional from the point of view of communication . . . And they do have a point, to be reached and negotiated as swiftly as possible . . . But there is hardly any novelty involved, even if (especially if?) the conversation becomes personal and garrulous. As a result, we have a series of utterances without interest . . . a static talking machine. (p. 199)

For Deleuze and Guattari, language used in conversation comes from the order-words of the dominant discourse that always disciplines what we can think and say. So what people say in ordinary conversation mostly echoes, repeats, dominant discourse.

Michel Foucault, too, made it clear in his archaeological and genealogical analyses that he was not interested in the conscious, knowing, rational, intentional speaking subject with its confessional tendencies. Much like Deleuze and Guattari, he focused instead on what was “given to the speaking subject” (Foucault, 1971/1972, p. 46) in the anonymous murmur of the discursive formations from which speech emerges, from the order of things, the grid of intelligibility that pre-exists an “I” created by language, an “I” who, once created, falsely believes it exists ahead of language and can speak with individual intention. We social scientists who want to do this “new” work and also want to base our science on the voices of our research participants might remember Foucault’s (1966/1970) project in his book, The Order of Things, which he explains in the following quotation:

I tried to explore scientific discourse not from the point of view of the individuals who are speaking, nor from the point of view of the formal structures of what they are saying, but from the point of view of the rules that come into play in the very existence of such discourse. (p. xiv)

Those interested in the new empiricisms, especially in the posthuman, must call into question the endless qualitative interviews that presume the humanist human, the cogito who can know and speak the truth, who can mean. The onto-epistemological formation that celebrates the speech of the humanist human and assigns it pre-eminent value and practical application as scientific discourse is not the onto-epistemological formation of post-qualitative inquiry. For that reason, those of us using poststructural theories should think, and should always have thought, twice before proposing research projects with, for example, an awkward combination of an interview study and a Foucaultian genealogy or a rhizo-analysis of interview data, projects that indicate ontological confusion.

What this comes down to, I believe, is that if one wants to move toward this new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative inquiry, one must begin anew with little “methodological” help—with no new empirical methods textbooks that describe research designs (recipes) and structuring practices that explain where to begin and what to do next and then next. In other words, to do this work, one must give up that sacred validating concept of science— systematicity—which is supposed to guarantee that qualitative methodology is rigorous science and not, say, journalism. To me, systematicity smacks of scientism. But Lyotard (1979/1984) explained the work of the postmodern artist or writer decades ago, and his description suits the work of new empirical inquiry. Lyotard wrote,

The text [the postmodern author] writes, the work he produces are not in principle governed by preestablished rules, and they cannot be judged according to a determining judgment, by applying familiar categories to the text or to the work. Those rules and categories are what the work of art itself is looking for. The artist and the writer, then, are working without rules in order to formulate the rules of what will have been done. Hence the fact that work and text have the character of an event; hence also, they always come too late for their author, or, what amounts to the same thing, their being put into work, their realization (mise en oeuvre) always begins too soon. (p. 81)

Interestingly, we seemed not to have understood Lyotard’s (and other poststructuralists’) comments about the postmodern as we diligently tried, for too long, to mix postmodern scholarship and methods-driven research. But the new empirical work makes it very clear that methodology and method can neither guide a research project nor guarantee its validity. In fact, the new empiricist might well argue that attempting to follow a given research method will likely foreclose possibilities for the “new.” The new empiricist researcher, then, is on her own, inventing inquiry in the doing.

But who wants to work so hard? Who wants to have to invent new empiricist inquiry and invent it anew for every study? A counter-question might be how we came to think we didn’t have to do that. Elliot Eisner (1996), who championed arts-based research, helped us think about difficult work and taking risks when he wrote that we should “work at the edge of incompetence” (p. 412), and Foucault (1984/1985) offered the following encouragement:

As to those for whom to work hard, to begin and begin again, to attempt and be mistaken, to go back and rework everything from top to bottom, and still find reason to hesitate from one step to the next— as to those, in short, for whom to work in the midst of uncertainty and apprehension is tantamount to failure, all I can say is that clearly we are not from the same planet. (p. 7)

Surely, this is the pleasure of scholarship, this not-knowing and, as Derrida (1980/1987) wrote, “knowing how not to be there and how to be strong for not being there right away. Knowing how not to deliver on command, how to wait and make wait” (p. 191). Perhaps not knowing and waiting describe the style of the new empirical researcher.

To sum up before moving on, I argue that much conventional humanist qualitative methodology, invented in the U.S. in the 1980s, was never able to make the interpretive turn and shed it’s positivist heritage. Further, the demands of scientifically based and evidence based research at the beginning of the 21st century restored and reinstalled positivism throughout the social sciences, especially in education. But qualitative research has always been another Enlightenment knowledge project focused on methodology and the production of knowledge. Typically, its structure and formalized practices have not only been weak epistemologically—for example, when researchers avoid theorizing and only “find themes in the data”—but also ontologically. What this means is that qualitative methodology seems to stand outside epistemology and ontology. But this kind of research has become all too familiar. Given that, it is very difficult for one well-trained in this kind of qualitative methodology to make the ontological turn toward new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative inquiry.

What is New in New Empirical Inquiry?

As I said earlier, I introduced the concept post qualitative inquiry in 2011 to encourage researchers to move past 1980s interpretive qualitative methodology, much of which I believe has been overtaken by positivism. In 2013, Patti Lather and I edited a special issue of the International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education on post qualitative inquiry. In 2014, Alecia Jackson and I edited a special issue of Qualitative Inquiry on qualitative data analysis after coding. Alecia Jackson, Lisa Mazzei, and I are currently editing a special issue of Cultural Studies-Critical Methodologies on the new empiricisms/new materialisms. Hillievi Lenz-Taguchi are editing a special issue of Qualitative Inquiry on using concepts instead of methods to guide our inquiry. Other special issues of journals as well as recent edited and authored books announce that scholars are taking up the challenges of new inquiry.

But in reviewing manuscripts submitted to journals in which authors claim to be doing new empirical, new material, posthuman, and post qualitative work, I find myself hard-pressed to see what’s “new” about much of it. It’s as if people try but can’t quite make the ontological turn, and I surely understand that. I’m not sure I can either. Like Maggie MacLure (2013), I believe the “shock” of working “within a materialist ontology has not yet been fully felt” (p. 663).

But whenever I’m interested in something new—to me, at least—I teach a course about it so my smart students can help me think. Two years ago I taught a new doctoral seminar, the “New Empiricisms and the New Materialisms,” and last year I taught again a doctoral seminar I developed in 2003 called “Post Qualitative Research,” the content of which has changed significantly over the years. In both courses, my students and I struggled to think about how to “do” social science inquiry differently if one thinks with those scholars we call poststructuralist as well as those writing more recently about the ontological and material turns. What would be new and different about that work? And where would one begin to do this “new” kind of inquiry? It’s all well and good to follow Deleuze and Guattari and say “begin in the middle”—even if that’s probably the best advice—but what does that look like? And how does a new researcher even know whether something is “new” and “different”? And how different do you have to be to be “new”? Do you have to invent an entire methodology or can you just struggle with what’s pressing in your own project? More practically, how can you increase your odds of doing something “new”?

With those questions in mind, I will next review how two theorists who critiqued humanist ontology, Foucault and Deleuze, described the “new.” Then, given their descriptions, I offer in the following section a few practices I think might be useful in getting us unstuck from conventional humanist qualitative methodology whose structure traps us and prevents us from making that ontological turn and moving toward the “new.”

I begin with Foucault (1971/1972) who wrote early in his career in his book, The Archaeology of Knowledge that “it is not easy to say something new.” Nonetheless, we know Foucault did say quite a few new things. He also said in an interview two years before he died at 54, “I worked like a dog all my life” (Foucault, 1982, p. 131) because his project was his own transformation. He said, “Do you think I have worked like that all those years to say the same thing and not to be changed”? This is interesting, isn’t it? Foucault’s warning us not only that doing something new is very hard work but that scholarly work is personal and not just academic. I agree and tell my students that if they’re working hard to read Foucault and Deleuze and Guattari and Derrida and Barad and Baudrillard and Bennett and Bergson and Spinoza, they will be changed, and they can’t go back. Thus, my advice to them is that if they’re especially fond of themselves as they are, they’d best avoid reading this literature on the “posts” and on ontology and go shopping or run a marathon instead.

John Rajchman (2008), discussing Deleuze’s (1986/1988) book on Foucault, explained that, for Foucault, the new is “not at all what is in fashion, but rather what we cannot yet see or say in what is happening in us just because it is not already contained in the … given [structures] that govern what we can think” (p. 89). We can’t see the new because of the structures of the present, and we have no language yet to say it. Almost a hundred years ago, Whitehead (1925) wrote that pre-existing structures normalize our thinking and produce “minds in a groove” (p. 197), but experimentation can help us move out of the grooves of the normal and self-evident. For Foucault, Rajchman (2008) explained, the new is “a pragmatic experimental matter, something we must actually do for which there precedes no determination, no model, no ‘we,’ not even an ‘I’” (p. 89). Again, there is no model—no method, no research design, nor an “I”— that exists ahead of experimental work that pushes toward the new and different.

Deleuze also believed that it is only in a practical and experimental engagement with the world that we can create something new because “the new is an outside that exists within this world, and as such it must be constructed” (O’Sullivan & Zepke, 2008, p. 2). For Deleuze (1968/1994), “the new, with its power of beginning and beginning again, remains forever new, just as the established was always established from the outset, even if a certain amount of empirical time was necessary for this to be recognized” (p. 136). So it may take some time to distinguish the new that is always becoming from the established that is. For this reason, the new can’t easily be recognized because it is outside our grids of intelligibility.

Most importantly, using language from major, structuring discourses (e.g., systematic science, methodological positivism, the solipsism of Cartesian knowledge projects) is dangerous because the language of those discourses does not work after the ontological turn (e.g., see MacLure, 2013; St.Pierre, in press). Major, dominant language describes what is recognizable, already captured, disciplined, and normalized—what is—not what is immanent but not yet, what could be becoming if we were able to resist the present and think and do it. That is Deleuze and Guattari’s (1991/1994) famous challenge: “We lack creation. We lack resistance to the present” (p. 108). Foucault’s (1982) challenge in regard to the present and, especially, to subjectivity is similar— we should “refuse what we are” (p. 216). In both cases, we must refuse order-words that enforce the present and, in this case, methodological order-words like method, systematicity, transparency, representation, validity, objectivity, and so on. These words force us into is.

Practices for the “New”

Why is it so difficult to take up the new empirical inquiry? As I’ve studied the manuscripts I review in which authors claim to be doing post qualitative work but aren’t and work with students who struggle to do something different, I’ve realized they often make the mistake of beginning with conventional humanist qualitative methodology. That is, they begin in a humanist instead of a posthumanist ontology. For example, they might include in the theoretical sections of their papers a smart discussion of DeleuzoGuattarian concepts they say informed their research, but then they proceed to describe their projects as conventional humanist qualitative studies using the ontological assumptions, language, and practices of that methodology. In effect, they simply drop one or two Deleuzian concepts into a qualitative study and, of course, the ontologies are incommensurable. I don’t see how these confused projects can produce anything “new.”

Why does this happen? I believe that in too much social science research, in the U.S., at least, we chiefly teach methodology, having separated it from epistemology and ontology, thereby reducing inquiry to method and research design. Hence, we have methods-driven research that mostly repeats what is recognizable, what is already known.

What we fail to teach is epistemology and ontology. We fail to teach theory. Why? I believe it’s easier to teach methods than theory. It’s easier to teach, say, five research designs than DeleuzoGuattarian ontology, which is very difficult to understand. Lecercle (2002) wrote that it took him thirty years to begin to understand Deleuze’s (1969/1990) book, The Logic of Sense. And you have to read Deleuze and Guattari’s (1980/1987) long book, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, which is not logically sequential, before you’re ready to read it. Again, who wants to work so hard?

Out of this, I have begun to recommend some specific practices that might increase our odds of accomplishing something “new” in new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative inquiry. I’ll discuss each of these practices in turn: refusing qualitative methodology, reading, beginning with theories and concepts instead of methodology, and trusting ourselves in not knowing. Of course, these practices are not radical but are, I would argue, age-old practices of solid scholarship.

First practice: Refuse qualitative methodology.

My first “practice for the new” in new empirical inquiry is to leave conventional humanist qualitative methodology behind, to refuse it. Those of us who’ve learned it too well will just have to try to forget it. We should remember that we invented this methodology in the 1980s—we made it up—and it’s not sacred. It’s simply one approach among others, and we can’t take it too seriously. The ontology of this methodology retains binaries like human/nonhuman, word/thing, representation/the real distinctions, which are unintelligible in new empirical inquiry in which “the separation between subject and object, thought and matter, words and things, is an illusion of language” (Lecercle, 2002, p. 27).

In short, I believe qualitative methodology is a trap for those who want to do new empirical inquiry. It traps us when we drop a concept like the rhizome or assemblage from Deleuze and Guattari’s experimental ontology into the structure of a humanist interview study that privileges the ontology of the “speaking subject.” It traps us when we retain concepts like data and subjectivity that are not thinkable in the same way, if at all, in an experimental ontology. In other words, using a concept from one ontology in another just doesn’t work. Those of us interested in the “post” theories spent many years deconstructing the concepts of conventional humanist qualitative inquiry—for example, interview, data, voice, validity, reflexivity—and working its ruins (St.Pierre & Pillow, 2000), but we remained trapped in those ruins, I believe, by not attending to ontological issues. I suggest we do something different from the beginning.

Second practice: Read, read, read.

I advise my students who want to do new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative work to shift their focus from methodology to onto-epistemology. Reading a few of the many texts that introduce qualitative, quantitative, and mixed methods research is sufficient. I encourage my students to spend their time reading and re-reading scholars who have written about onto-epistemology for centuries. This reading is the true pleasure of our lives as academics, and I believe inquiry begins by reading what Foucault (1971/1972) called the “already said” (p. 25) that may well be “new” for us and give us language and strategies to think and do our own “new.”

I tell my doctoral students, “No one can read for you. You have to do it yourself. And those who read a lot can always tell when others don’t.” I tell them that the most voracious readers know that the image of thought within which we comfortably think and live may well be demolished by reading the next book or journal article and that, at some point, that “shock to thought” (Massumi, 2002) is our desire. I caution them about reading too many books they understand. I encourage them to organize reading groups to read books that are too hard to read and to set up what I call “reading management strategies” (see St.Pierre, 2014) to keep track of their reading so they can use it later for writing.

I tell that if they keep reading, if they read and read and read, if they let the words and concepts wash over them, they will, indeed, begin to put them to work in their everyday lives. They will understand what Foucault meant when he said we have to give up the “we” and the “I.” They’ll understand why Deleuze refused the personal pronouns. They will no longer believe or live the human/nonhuman binary.

At some point, they begin to understand the impossibility of “human subjects research” as conceived by conventional humanist qualitative methodology. Instead, they grapple with theory, for example, with Deleuze and Guattari’s (1980/1987) shocking ontological statement, “There is no longer a tripartite division between a field of reality (the world) and a field of representation (the book) and a field of subjectivity (the author)” (p. 23). In this flattened ontology, human bodies, other living bodies, objects, language, representations, concepts like revenge, values like goodness, dreams, the color green, a memory, the weather, five-o’clock in the afternoon, and the not-yet are mixed, entangled on the surface. There is no depth in this ontology as in structuralism and phenomenology. The human is no longer prior to language, method, and the world; in fact, the human being of humanism is no longer intelligible.

It is impossible to think humanist “human subjects research” when, to simplify Deleuze and Guattari, we are always assemblages that are not stable entities that can be broken down into distinct component parts and made to mean but, rather something like machines that are constantly territorializing and deterritorializing—becoming. Importantly, assemblages do not imply interiority but exteriority, so we would not ask what an assemblage is or what parts it contains but rather with what it connects, what it plugs into. Again, human being is not independent and self-contained but mixed with everything else on the surface. We cannot separate out the human subject in posthuman, new empirical, new material, post qualitative inquiry. Our responsibility is no longer to the privileged human but to the assemblage which is always more-than-human and always becoming. In this age of the Anthropocene, responsibility assumes its full meaning.

This brief description gestures toward the ontological image of thought that guides the new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative work and displaces humanist qualitative inquiry. At the heart of this ontology are very different understandings of language and human being that we must account for. Once those two concepts in humanist ontology are shattered, we no doubt flounder; but it is from that not knowing that the “new” might emerge. Of course, the poststructuralists told us this decades ago, but, stuck in the groove of humanist qualitative methodology, we somehow mostly ignored that profound rupture.

I surely did not understand Deleuze’s and Deleuze and Guattari’s work together when I first read it early in my doctoral studies—not in a university course but on my own—nor do I “understand” it now. Nonetheless, the image of thought enabled by their concepts like haecceity, assemblage, and Bodies without Organs stuck with me, ruining conventional humanist qualitative methodology from the start. I am grateful I read Deleuze and Guattari, Butler, Spivak, Foucault, Baudrillard, Lyotard, Derrida, and others we call “post” before I was over-trained in humanist qualitative methodology, before its methods-driven structure took over my thought and practices.

Third practice: Begin with theory and concepts.

So if, for example, a doctoral student has avoided learning too much conventional humanist qualitative methodology and has, instead, studied onto-epistemology, what might she do next for her dissertation research? She may well panic because her classmates may have begun their studies by following the clear instructions of the many books and journal articles that describe the “research process” in quantitative, qualitative, or mixed methods studies. They have a well-trod path to follow.

To repeat, I advise students not to begin with methodology but with theory(ies) or a concept or several related concepts they’ve identified in their reading that helps them think about whatever they’re interested in thinking about, for example, reluctant readers, the quantified student, a painting (see, e.g., Jackson & Mazzei, 2012). So if a student is interested in Foucault’s theory of power, she should read everything he wrote about power as well as secondary sources and critiques. If she’s interested in Deleuze’s work on the image in cinema, she should read everything he wrote about it as well as secondary sources and critique. The same would hold for any theory or concept the researcher chooses to help her think. In Deleuze and Guattari’s work, one concept is seldom enough because their concepts are entangled, just like their ontology. The point here is that sustained and what Judith Butler (1995) called careful reading is required and brings some measure of confidence and expertise so that students understand why they cannot carelessly mix ontologies.

To repeat, the theory(ies) and/or the concept(s), then, guides the study instead of a pre-determined methodology. From among many concepts, the researcher chooses those that help her think about whatever she wants to think about. She plugs concepts into the world to see how they work. If she’s studied the theory in depth, good questions to ask when confused about what to do might be “What would Foucault do?” “Would Derrida code data?” “Would Lyotard use the concept triangulation?” And the best thing to do when confused is to go back to the texts and re-read the theory, to plunge into the words of scholars who inspire.

I am not especially concerned with classifying or labeling this kind of inquiry, because post-method, “after method” (Law, 2004), every study will be different and unclassifiable, which will no doubt make some uneasy. They might ask, “What is this study?” We’ll have to train ourselves not to look for prescribed method, familiar practices of formalization, and tortured systematicity in this work. We’ll have to read each individual study carefully to see what that particular researcher did, why, and to what effect. We’ll have to be open to the “new,” to what we might not understand because we aren’t familiar with a particular theory or concept. We will not be able to judge every study by some pre-existing standard invented decades ago to discipline a different kind of inquiry. Most importantly, we will have to help each other think, and think differently.

Fourth practice: Trust yourself and get to work.

The fourth practice I recommend to students, after they’ve given up qualitative methodology, have read and read and read, and have found theory(ies) and/or concept(s) to guide their inquiry, is to trust themselves. I encourage them to just put to work the practices the theories and concepts enable—we might call these conceptual practices (Harding, 2007; Smith, 1990)—to do the next thing experimental ontology enables them to think and do. The idea is that the theory or the concept calls on you to do some things but not others. If you’re thinking with Deleuze’s ontological concept, assemblage, for example, I don’t think you can “collect data” because assemblage tells you that you’ve never been separate from data. Data is not something out there separate from the human that can be “collected.” The human and the rest of the world have always been entangled, mixed together. So you have to give up the concept data and the conceptual practice data collection because they are intelligible only in a humanist ontology and methodology.

So what else might you do if you don’t collect data? I have no idea, but, clearly, you’re working in a very different image of thought now with no established rules and practices. And your conceptual practices will be what you do with your concept when you plug it into your world. When someone else plugs assemblage into the world of their project, they might use the same conceptual practices, but they may not. In other words, there’s nothing right or correct to be done before the doing. You’re on your own here. And I tell my students they have to be really smart when they do this work. They can’t just casually throw these concepts around. They have to really understand the DeleuzoGuattarian ontology in which the concept assemblage works so they can provide the rationale for what they do, why, and how. In other words, their conceptual practices must align with the onto-epistemology they’re using.

But I suspect many conceptual practices we use in new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative inquiry will be quite familiar, what we do when we want to explore anything. For example, we read, we write, we talk with other people, we observe what’s going on around us. We may make a movie, paint a picture, write a book— who knows? In the name of positivist social science, which now permeates conventional humanist qualitative methodology in the U.S., we have overdetermined, over-formalized, systematized, and scientized some everyday practices out of all proportion to legitimate them as “scientific,” but we have completely ignored others. For example, in conventional humanist qualitative methodology, we’ve mostly reduced research practices to two “methods of data collection,” interviews and observations, though, as I just said, I doubt the concepts “data” or “methods of data collection” are thinkable in new empirical inquiry in which the human has never been separate from “data,” outside it, so she could “collect” it. The language of qualitative methodology surely traps us, doesn’t it?

My point here is that ordinary practices like talking with and observing people don’t have to be scientized and elevated to the status of “the interview” and “the observation.” I’ve always been interested in all the other practices we neglect to disclose, all the other things we do that we never describe in our research reports. For example, when I’m deep into a project and stuck, I go for a walk or weed my garden and inevitably get unstuck, so I suppose I could call walking and weeding research practices—but why would I? And, surely, we could name reading a research practice, but we don’t—we call it the “literature review.” I’m very interested in the conceptual practices concepts like diagram, Bodies without Organs, entanglement, and vital matter enable. What would one do if one were thinking and living with those concepts?

My strongest recommendation today is that we not to try to force our new empirical, new material, posthuman, post qualitative studies into the structure of conventional humanist qualitative methodology. I can’t imagine how it could fit. Instead of beginning with methodology, I recommend putting the concepts and theories of experimental ontology to work using the conceptual practices that are appropriate for a particular study. If we’ve done our reading, I wager we cannot not put it to work. It will have transformed us—we cannot think and live without it. We will be living it.

As Foucault and Deleuze explained, the “new” is already in our lives, but repetition of the same cannot create it. We have to make it. It is in the experimental moment of not knowing what to do next because we are not driven by method and methodology that we might push through the grooves of the given and the self-evident toward the new and different in our work and lives. Method, then, will always come at the end, too late, when we think back about what we did and why and what we might have done instead and might try next time.

 

References

Barad, K. (2010). Quantum entanglements and hauntological relations of inheritance: Dis/continuities, spacetime infoldings, and justice-to-come. Derrida Today, 3(2), pp. 240-268.

Braidotti, R. (2013).   The posthuman. Cambridge, England: Polity Press.

Brown, B. (2001). Thing theory. Critical Inquiry, 28(1), 1-22.

Butler, J. (1995). For a careful reading. In S. Benhabib, J. Butler, D. Cornell & N. Fraser (Eds.). Feminist contentions: A philosophical exchange (pp. 127-143). New York, NY: Routledge.

Clough, P.T. (2009). The new empiricism: Affect and sociological method. European Journal of Social Theory, 12(1): 43-61.

Coole, D. & Frost, S. (Eds.). (2010). New materialisms: Ontology, agency, and politics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

De Landa, M. (2006). A new philosophy of society: Assemblage theory and social complexity. New York, NY: Continuum.

Deleuze, G. (1988). Foucault. (S. Hand, Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. (Original work published 1986)

Deleuze, G. (1990). The logic of sense. (C. V. Boundas, Ed., M. Lester, Trans.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press. (Original work published 1969)

Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophrenia. (B. Massumi, Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. (Original work published 1980)

Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and repetition. (P. Patton, Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press. (Original work published 1968)

Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F. (1994). What is philosophy? (H. Tomlinson & G. Burchell, Trans.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press. (Original work published 1991)

Denzin, N. K. (1989). Interpretive interactionism. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.

Derrida, J. (1980). The post card: From Socrates to Freud and beyond. (A. Bass, Trans.). Chicago: IL: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1987)

Elliot E., in Saks, A.L. (1996). Viewpoints: Should novels count as dissertations in education? Research in the Teaching of English, 30 (4), 403-427.

Erickson, F. (1986). Qualitative methods in research on teaching. In M. C. Wittrock (Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching (3rd ed.), (pp. 119- 161). New York, NY: Macmillan.

Foucault, M. (1970). The order of things: An archaeology of the human sciences. (A.M.S. Smith, Trans). New York, NY: Vintage Books. (Original work published 1966)

Foucault, M. (1972). The archaeology of knowledge and the discourse on language (A.M.S. Smith, Trans.). New York, NY: Pantheon Books. (Original work published 1971)

Foucault, M. (1982). The subject and power. In H. L. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics. (2nd ed.), (pp. 208-226). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Foucault, M. (1985). The history of sexuality. Volume 2. The use of pleasure. (R. Hurley, Trans.). New York, NY: Vintage Books. (Original work published 1984)

Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures: Selected essays. New York, NY: Basic Books.

Gregg, M. & Seigworth, G. J. (Eds.). (2010). The affect theory reader. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Harding, S. (2007). Feminist standpoints. In S.N. Hesse-Biber (Ed.), Handbook of feminist research: Theory and praxis, (pp. 45-69). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Jackson, A. Y. & Mazzei L. A. (2012). Thinking with theory in qualitative research: Viewing data across multiple perspectives. London, UK: Routledge.

Kirby, V. (2011). Quantum anthropologies: Life at large. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Law, J. (2004). After method: Mess in social science research. London, England: Routledge.

Lecercle, J-J. (2002). Deleuze and language. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

Lincoln, Y. S. & Guba, E. G. (1985). Naturalistic inquiry. Newbury Park: Sage.

Lyotard, J-F. (1984). The postmodern condition: A report on knowledge. (G. Bennington & B. Massumi, Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. (Original work published 1979)

MacLure, M. (2013). Researching without representation? Language and materiality in post-qualitative methodology. International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education, 26(6), 658-667.

Massumi, B. (Ed.). (2002). A shock to thought: Expression after Deleuze and Guattari. London, England: Routledge.

National Research Council. (2014). Proposed Revisions to the Common Rule for the Protection of Human Subjects in the Behavioral and Social Sciences. Committee on Revisions to the Common Rule for the Protection of Human Subjects in Research in the Behavioral and Social Sciences. Board on Behavioral, Cognitive, and Sensory Sciences, Committee on National Statistics, Division of Behavioral and Social Sciences and Education. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

O’Sullivan, S. & Zepke, S. Introduction: The problem of the new. In S. O’Sullivan & S. Zepke (Eds.). (2008). Deleuze, Guattari and the production of the new (pp. 1-10). New York, NY: Continuum.

Pascale, C-M.. (2011) Cartographies of knowledge: Exploring qualitative epistemologies. Los Angeles, CA: Sage.

Rajchman, J. (1985). Michel Foucault: The freedom of philosophy. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

Rajchman, J. (2008). A portrait of Deleuze-Foucault. In S. O’Sullivan & S. Zepke (Eds.). (2008). Deleuze, Guattari and the production of the new (pp. 80-90). New York, NY: Continuum.

Smith, D. (1990). The conceptual practices of power: A feminist sociology of knowledge. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press.

Steinmetz, G. (2005). The epistemological unconscious of U.S. sociology and the transition to post-Fordism: The case of historical sociology (pp. 109-157). In J. Adams, E.S. Clemens, & A.S. Orloff (Eds.), Remaking modernity: Politics, history, sociology, (pp. 109-157). Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

St.Pierre, E. A. (1997). Methodology in the fold and the irruption of transgressive data. International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education, 10(2), 175-189.

St.Pierre, E. A. & Pillow W. S. (Eds.). (2000). Working the ruins: Feminist poststructural theory and methods in education. New York, NY: Routledge.

St.Pierre, E.A. (2008). Decentering voice in qualitative inquiry. In A.Y. Jackson & L. Mazzei (Eds.), Voice in qualitative inquiry: Challenging conventional, interpretive, and critical conceptions (pp. 221-236). New York: Routledge.

St.Pierre, E.A. (2011a). Post qualitative research: The critique and the coming after. In N.K. Denzin & Y.S. Lincoln (Eds.). Sage handbook of qualitative inquiry (4th ed.) (pp. 611-635). Los Angeles, CA: Sage.

St.Pierre, E.A. (2011b). Refusing human being in humanist qualitative inquiry. In N.K. Denzin & M.D. Giardina (Eds.), Qualitative inquiry and the global crisis (pp. 40-55). Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press.

St.Pierre, E.A. (2014). An always already absent collaboration. Cultural Studies-Critical Methodologies. 14 (4), 374-379.

St.Pierre, E.A. (in press). Deleuze and Guattari’s language for new empirical inquiry. Educational Philosophy and Theory.

Whitehead, A.N. (1925). Science and the modern world [Lowell Lectures, 1925]. New York, NY. The Free Press.

One thought on “Wall in English

  1. I gave https://www.cornbreadhemp.com/collections/cbd-cream a prove payment the cardinal previously, and I’m amazed! They tasted distinguished and provided a sense of calmness and relaxation. My stress melted away, and I slept less ill too. These gummies are a game-changer an eye to me, and I highly recommend them to anyone seeking unconstrained pain relief and improved sleep.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *